Stoic theory of universals

Realism1

Plato and Aristotle discussing universals in `School of Athens' by Raphael.

Plato and Aristotle in `School of Athens’ by Raphael.

The problem of universals is the problem of correspondence of our intellectual concepts to things existing outside our intellect. A universal is a property or relation that can be shared by a number of different particular things. Each yellow object participates, for example, in universal ‘yellowness’. Several attitudes towards the existence of universals are possible. The Stoics are nominalists and deny the existence of universals. Plato and Aristotle, on the other hand, are realists about universals because they assert that when we assign a property to a particular object—for example ‘this lemon is yellow’ and ‘this car is yellow’—that there actually exists something that is ‘yellowness’, shared by the lemon and the car. A realist about universals thus claims that when a is F and b is F, there is some extra-mental and extra-linguistic thing—the universal F-ness—that is had by both a and b. Both Plato and Aristotle argued that if knowledge or understanding (epistêmê) is to be possible, then there must be universals. Both disagreed however on where and how the universals exist (Question 2 and 3).

Plato’s theory of Forms

The distinction between Forms (eîdos or idéa) and sensible particular things is central to Plato’s metaphysics. Plato makes a clear distinction in the Timaeus between that which ‘always is and has no becoming’ and ‘that which is always becoming and never is’ (Timaeus 28a).2 This distinction has, according to Plato, epistemological consequences:

… that which is apprehended by intelligence (nous) and reason (logos) is always in the same state; but that which is conceived by opinion (doxa) with the help of sensation and without reason, is always in a process of becoming and perishing and never really is.3

The text-book account of Plato’s philosophy is that his theory of Forms is a reaction to the philosophy of Heraclitus, who argued that sensible particulars are always in a state of flux.4 The argument for Forms from Heracliteanism, which might thus be credited to Plato, is:

  1. What we understand when we understand what justice, beauty, or generally F-ness are, doesn’t ever change;
  2. But the sensible F particulars that exhibit these features are always changing;
  3. So there must be a non-sensible universal—the Form of F-ness—that we understand when we achieve epistime.

The question that needs to be asked of Plato is how much change is acceptable for any particular thing, for example a wombat, to remain a wombat? Any living wombat is always undergoing change of some kind, even if it is only chemical changes involved in the digestion of its lunch. This seems to rule out that in understanding the definition of a wombat, one could be understanding any particular wombat. What we understand when we understand the definition of a wombat is the existence of some kind of ‘über-wombat’, existing outside the realm of physical reality, not the particular—ever changing—wombat in nature.

Aristotle versus Plato

Both Plato and Aristotle are realists about universals. They however hold a different view about the relationship between the existence of universals and the particulars that participate in them. Scholastic philosophers described Plato’s theory as universalia ante rem (prior to things) and they wrote that Aristotle had a theory of universalia in re (in things). This implies that Plato thought that universal properties can exist even if there were no particulars participating in them—universals are transcendent to the world. Aristotle on the other hand thought that there can not be any universals unless there are also particulars participating in them—universals are immanent in the world. The difference in their theories is beautifully expressed in the School of Athens by Raphaelo Stanzio (1483–1520). In this fresco, Plato and Socrates are in the centre of the composition, with Plato pointing to the heavens and Aristotle pointing towards the earth.

Stoics against the realists

The Stoic ‘not-someone’ argument is a continuation of Aristotle’s objection that if the Form of beauty could exist independently of beautiful particulars, it would itself have to be a particular. By this Aristotle seems to have meant that, if the Form of, for example, a chiliagon (a thousand sided figure, from: chilias—one thousand) could exist independently of any chiliagon-shaped things, then it would be a kind of super-sensible particular thing. The ‘not-someone’ argument is—according to the Neoplatonic philosopher Simplicus (527–565 AD)—invoked by the Stoics to disprove that universals are a ‘this something’, e.g. they neither exist nor subsist:5

  1. Man is someone;
  2. If someone is in Athens, he is not in Megara;
  3. But man is in Athens;
  4. Therefore man is not in Megara.

Seddley explains that: ‘If you make the mistake of hypostasing the universal man into a Platonic abstract universal—if you regard him as a someone—you will be unable to resist the evidently fallacious syllogism’.6 The improper step is the substitution of man with someone. The argument can be fixed only by denying that universal man is ‘someone’ and subsequently that universals do not exist separately from particulars.

The Stoics distinguish two different ways of getting to know what is in the world. They are materialists in that they believe that only bodies exist. Meanings, time, place and void however, don’t exist but subsist (huparchein). We could render the Stoic distinction between exist and subsist by saying that ‘There is such a thing as a rainbow, and such a character as Mickey Mouse, but they don’t actually exist.’7 The Stoics say that the highest genus under which everything falls is not ‘existence’ or ‘being’ but ‘something’.8 Any particular thing that can sensibly be talked about is a something, but not all somethings exist in the Stoic sense of the word. They introduced this terminology is to explain phenomena that we believe have some kind of being (such as meanings, time, place and void), but fall short of the kind of being which is familiar to us from our interactions with spatially located bodies. Universals are a ‘not something’ to the Stoics because they neither exist nor subsist. The Stoics say that universals (concepts) are ‘neither somethings nor qualified, but figments of the soul which are quasi-somethings and quasi-qualified’.9

Against Nominalism

According to the nominalist, for a particular to have a property is for it to stand in a certain relation to a kind of mental of linguistic thing, a concept or predicate. David Armstrong thinks that this makes the question of what properties particulars have a matter of how we classify things. He further argues that our categories are independent of the actual properties of objects.10 Whether for example the throwing of a brick will break the window depends on the impulse of the brick (mass and velocity), the plasticity indices of the brick and the glass and the thickness of the glass. The brick would break the window, even if we had no concepts such as impulse and plasticity index. Armstrong thus argues that basic properties exist independently and are not a matter of the classifications we make. The nominalist will, in response to Armstrongs critique, simply deny that their view implies that we construct the world with our concepts in any way that negates the objectivity of relations of cause and effect. They hold that our classifications depend on and react to objective resemblances between things. Armstrong anticipates this objection by arguing that resemblance is so far from providing an alternative to universals that it actually presupposes them. Armstrong explains resemblance by appealing to shared universals. The resemblance nominalist takes resemblance as a ‘brute matter of fact’, but everyone must take something as a brute matter of fact, even Armstrong.11

Notes


  1. This short essay has been written as an undergraduate paper for Monash University. 

  2. Plato, Timaeus, (The Intenet Classics Archive, 1994). 

  3. Ibid. 28a. 

  4. ‘Upon those that step into the same rivers different and different waters flow …’, Arius Didymus, in: G.S. Kirk, J.E. Raven, and M. Schoffield, The presocratic philosophers, 2nd edition. (Cambridge University Press, 1983), pp. 194–195. 

  5. Simplicus, On Aristotle’s categories, cited in: A.A. Long and D.N. Sedley, The Hellenistic philosophers, Volume 1, (Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 180, §30E. 

  6. David Sedley, ‘The Stoic theory of universals’, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 23(185). 

  7. Long and Sedley (1987), p. 164. 

  8. Seneca, Letters, cited in: Ibid., p. 162, §27A. 

  9. Stobaeus, cited in: Ibid., p. 179, §30A. 

  10. D.M. Armstrong, Universals and scientific realism, (Cambridge, 1978). 

  11. Carl Brock Sides, Nominalism. D. M. Armstrong’s arguments against various sorts of nominalism, 1997. 

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *